• Shuffle
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Alphabetize
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Front First
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Both Sides
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Read
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
Reading...
Front

Card Range To Study

through

image

Play button

image

Play button

image

Progress

1/46

Click to flip

Use LEFT and RIGHT arrow keys to navigate between flashcards;

Use UP and DOWN arrow keys to flip the card;

H to show hint;

A reads text to speech;

46 Cards in this Set

  • Front
  • Back
  • 3rd side (hint)

Inductive Argument

Decitates how we can infer from observed events to generalizations we can rely on.

An inductive argument can't guarantee that the truth of its premises will transfer to its conclusion.

Logic

The science which addresses the validity of inference and demonstration.


So it's an attempt to explain in as systematic way as possible what the principles of valid reasoning are.


Deductive Argument

An argument on which the conclusion is entailed by the premises. The conclusion follows because of the form of the argument rather than the meaning the terms.

The conclusion is deduced by the premises. The premises serve to prove the conclusion. Cannot lead from true premises to false conclusions. The arguments validity is completely independant of the truth of the statements that make it up. An argument whose premises are false and conclusion is true can be valid. An argument whose premises are false and conclusion are false can also be valid. But a deductive argument that has true premises but a false conclusion is invalid.

Law of Noncontradiction

No proposition can be both true and false.

Aristotelian logic fundamental principle. One of two.

Law of the Excluded Middle

A proposition must either be true or false.

Aristotelian logic fundamental principle. One of two.

Syllogism

A form of argument with two premises and a conclusion, such as all men are mortal; Socrates is a man, therefore Socrates is mortal.

All A's are B's, all B's are C's, therefore all A's are C's. The conclusion is deduced by the premises. The premises serve to prove the conclusion. Aristotelian syllogism is based mostly on deductive syllogism but also touches on inductive argument as part of the science of reasoning.

Indicator Word

Indicates the logical relationship of claims that come before or after it.

Because, therefore, so, hence, thus, it follows that, as a result, consequently, etc. indicate conclusion statements. Since, if, because, from which it follows, for these reasons, etc. indicate premises.

Good Arguement

An argument that gives us good reasons (premises) to believe the conclusion. Depends on whether the premises are true and the conclusion follows from the premises.

Two conditions: Truth Condition - All premises must be true. Logic Condition - The conclusion must follow from the premises.

Valid Argument

An argument where if all the premises are true, the conclusion cannot be false. If all the premises are true, the conclusion follows with certainty.

One of the ways to fulfill the logic condition. Validity is a logical property of whole arguments, not of individual claims. All A are B. X is an A. Therefore, X is a B.

Invalid Argument

If all the premises are true, the conclusion can be false.


It is logically possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false.


The truth of the premises does not guarantee the truth of the conclusion.

Strong Argument

An argument in which the if the premises are true, they strongly suggest the truth of the conclusion. If all the premises are true, the conclusion follows with high probability.

One of the ways to meet the logic condition. A strong argument can be invalid. The distinction between strong and week arguments is a matter of degree based on conventional choice. Most A are B. X is an A. Therefore, X is a B. Almost all A are B. X is an A. Therefore, X is a B.

Weak Argument

An argument where the if the premises are true, they do not strongly suggest the truth of the conclusion. If all the premises are true, the conclusion follows neither with certainty nor with high probability. They do not follow the logic condition.

In this case, the premise is not strong enough to imply the conclusion. Some A are B. X is an A. Therefore, X is a B.

Claim

Declarative statement. When one claim is made and other claims are added as evidence to support the truth of another claim then the claims together become an argument.

Bats are mammals. Good exists. There are two inches of snow on my car.

Argument

One or more claims (premises) intended to support the truth of another claim (conclusion).

Inferences

Evaluations that can be made regardless of whether the premises are true.

Technical Definition

Stipulate technical definitions to define how you intend to use the word.

Argument Form

The logical structure of an argument which are templates into which meaningful claims can be inserted.

Modus Ponens

Logical structure whereas: if P, then Q. P. Therefore, Q.

Modus Tollens

A logical structure whereas: if P, then Q. Not Q. Therefore, not P.

Sentences

In logic, they are the statements that can be true or false and are put together to form the premises and conclusion of an argument.

The sentences can reflect either fact or opinion. Questions, imperatives, and exclamations do not count as logical sentence claims.

Questions

In logic, questions themselves do not count as sentences, but answers will because answers are true or false.

Imperatives

Commands are neither true or false and do not count as sentences in logic. Not all commands are phrased as imperatives which allows them to be true or false and recognized as sentences in logic. 'You will respect my authority.'

Exclamations

Exclamations do not add to logical sentences and do not make up logical sentences. Sentences are focused on statements that can either be true or false. 'Oouch!' is neither true or false.

Extraneous Material

Anything in a passage that does not do rational work in an argument, that is, words or phrases that do not play a role in a premise or the conclusion.

Set Up / Background Phrases

Type of extraneous material.

Once again... to begin... let me say a few words about... as you are well aware...

Expressions of Personal Feeling or Commentary

Type of extraneous material.

It happens over and over... some of the worst... rears its ugly head... its pretty obvious... it should be clear that... i can't believe... it's really sad that... i would like to propose that...

Transition Phrases

Type of extraneous material.

In addition... which leads me to my next point... on one hand... on the other hand... insofar as... naturally... of course... didn't you know... you know... that raises the question... which leads us to ask...

Buzz Words

Words or phrases that seem meaningful, even technical and academic, but that have no meaning at all.

When buzz words are not explicitly defined in a particular context, they have only the pretense of meaning.

Ambiguous

A word or phrase that has more than one clear meaning.

There are two types: lexical ambiguity, and syntactic ambiguity.

Lexicaly Ambiguous

A word that has more than one clear meaning.

Match, pen, chip, suit, virus, hard, draw, head, mouse, bank.

Syntactically Ambiguous

A phrase in which the arrangement of words allows for more than one clear interpretation.

I cancelled my travel plans to play golf.


My travel plans included playing golf but I cancelled those plans.


I cancelled my travel plans in order to play golf.

Vagueness

A weird or phrase that has clear meaning, but does not precisely define truth conditions.

Tall, short, close, far, weak, strong, soft, hard, fat, thin, pile, heap.

Truth Conditions

Conditions on which we could say for sure that the claim in which the word is used is true or false.

Propositional Logic

Deals with logical relationships between propositions taken as wholes. It is interested in how the truth value of compound claims depends on the truth value of the individual claims that make it up. The compound claim as a whole can be true or false and the individual statements in the compound claim can be individually true or false. If either component is false the entire compound claim is false.

Sometimes called sentential logic or statement logic. In logic we use letters to symbolize propositions (statements, sentences, assertions).

Compound Claims

Claims that are made up of more than one statement that can be true or false. If one statement in the compound claim is false then the whole claim is false. The compound claim is true when all claims are true.

Basic claim structures:


A and B (conjunction)


A or B (disjunction)


If A then B (conditional)


Not-A (contradictory)

Conjunctions

A and B


A but B


A however B


A yet B


A and B and C but D and E

Only true if all of the individual claims are true.

Disjunctions

A or B


A or B or C or D or E


Inclusive Or claims are only false if all claims are false.


Exclusive Or claims are false if either all claims are false or all claims are true since one claim negates the other in a valid exclusive or claim.

Asserts that at least one claim of a set of claims is true. There are inclusive or statements and exclusive or statements. Inclusive or statements do not negate the truth values of the other claims in a sentence, meaning they are not mutually exclusive. In an exclusive or statement only one of the claims can be true.

Conditionals

If A then B (A -> B)


Assert a logical relationship between A and B. Does not assert that A is true or B is true, just the logical relationship between the two. The only time a conditional is not true is when the antecedent is true and the conditional is false.

Conditional claims have two parts consisting of the antecedent and the consequent. The antecedent is the claim that comes right after the if in a conditional claim and the consequent is the claim that comes after the then.

Conditional Fallacy

Fallacies that occur in interpreting conditional statements.

Affirming The Consequent: If A then B. B so A. Just because B is true doesn't mean A is true.


Bioconditionals

A if and only if B


A iff B


A<-->


A=B


(If B then A) and (if A then B)


Joins two conditionals using the if rule and only if rule.


It asserts two things: that A is true if B is true. And that A is true only if B is true.

The truth of the claims has to run both ways. If A then B and if B then A.

Sentence Letters SL

Capital letters are used to represent basic sentences. Whatever logical structure a sentence might have is lost when it is translated as an atomic sentence.

Requires the use of a symbolization key which provides and English language sentence for each sentence letter used in the symbolization.

Atomic Sentences

The sentences that can be symbolized with sentence letters. If A is true, then -¡A is false. If -¡A is true, then A is false.

A subscript is added after the letter since the English alphabet is finite and there is no limit to the number of atomic sentences.

Connectives

Logical connectives are used to build complex sentences from atomic components.

There are 5 logical connectives in SL:


‐¡ negation "it is not the case that"


& conjunction "both... and..."


V disjunction "either... or..."


--> conditional "if... then..."


<-> biconditional "... if and only if..."

Negation

A sentence can be symbolized as -¡A if it can be paraphrased in English as "it is not the case that A."


B: Mary is in Barcelona


-¡B: Mary is not in Barcelona. Mary is somewhere besides Barcelona.


R: The widget is replaceable.


-¡-¡R The widget is not irreplaceable.


H: Elliot is happy.


Incorrect: -¡H Elliot is unhappy. Just because Elliot is not happy doesn't mean Elliot is unhappy. So to represent Elliot is unhappy would require a new letter symbol. -¡ would have to mean it is not the case that Elliot is happy. He could be not happy but that doesn't imply he's unhappy. He could be in between.

Conjunction

Two claims joined by 'and.' A sentence can be symbolized as A & B if it can be paraphrased in English as "both A, and B." Each of the conjuncts must be a sentence. Sentences that can be paraphrased "A, but B" or "although A, B" are best symbolized using conjunction A & B. A & B is true if and only if both A and B are true.

The individual claims in a conjunction are called conjuncts. Words like both and also do not add to the logical structure of claims so they do not require symbols.

Disjunctive

Claims separated by 'or.' A sentence can be symbolized as A V B if it can be paraphrased in English as "either A, or B." Each of the disjuncts must be a sentence. There are exclusive 'or' sentences that imply that the truth of one claim results in the negation of the other claim. Inclusive 'or' sentences allow room for both claims to be possible in the existence of the truth of an individual claim. It implies that at least one of the claims are true and that doesn't make the other claims false. A disjunct is only false if all claims are false.

Like conjunction, disjunctions are also logically symmetrical.