• Shuffle
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Alphabetize
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Front First
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Both Sides
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Read
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
Reading...
Front

Card Range To Study

through

image

Play button

image

Play button

image

Progress

1/39

Click to flip

Use LEFT and RIGHT arrow keys to navigate between flashcards;

Use UP and DOWN arrow keys to flip the card;

H to show hint;

A reads text to speech;

39 Cards in this Set

  • Front
  • Back

Preference relation

Binary relation that is complete and transitive

Utility function existence (binary relation must be...)

... complete, transitive, continuous, strictly monotonic

Completeness

for all x1 and x2, either x1 >~ x2 or x2 >~ x1

Transitivity

if x1 >~ x2 and x2 >~ x3, then x1 >~ x3

Continuity

>~(x) and <~(x) are closed




implies ~(x) is closed b/c it is the intersection of these two

Strict monotonicity

if x0 >= x1 then x0 >~ x1 and if x0 >> x1 then x0 > x1

Convexity

If x1 >~ x0 then t x1 + (1 - t) x0 >~ x0 for all t in [0,1]

Invariance of utility to positive monotonic transformation

if and only if!!!

Properties of preferences and utility functions

1. u(x) is strictly increasing iff >~ is strictly monotonic


2. u(x) is quasiconcave iff >~ convex


3. u(x) strictly quasiconcave iff >~ strictly convex

MRS

absolute value of indifference curve through point




indifference curve: u(x1, f(x1)) = constant


MRS = -f'(x1)

Indirect utility function

demand: x(p, y)




v(p, y) = u(x(p, y))

Properties of indirect utility function

if u(x) is continuous and strictly increasing, then v(p, y) is:




1. Continuous


2. Homogeneous degree 0 in (p, y)


3. Strictly increasing in y


4. Decreasing in p


5. Quasiconvex in (p, y)


6. Roy's identity:


x_i(p0, y0) = -(dv(p0, y0)/dp_i) / (dv(p0, y0)/dy)

Expenditure function

hicksian demand: x^h(p, u)




e(p, u) = p * x^h(p, u)

Properties of the expenditure function

If u is continuous and strictly increasing, then e(p, u):




1. e(p, 0) = 0


2. continuous


3. if p >> 0, strictly increasing and unbounded above in u


4. increasing in p


5. homogeneous degree 1 in p


6. concave in p


7. Shephard's lemma:


de(p0, u0) / dp_i = x_i^h(p0, u0)

Relation between indirect utility and expenditure

e(p, v(p, y)) = y


v(p, e(p, u)) = u




e(p, u) = v^-1(p; u)


v(p, y) = e^-1(p; y)

Core of exchange economy

set of all unblocked feasible allocations

Unique demand

if u is continuous, strongly increasing, and strictly quasiconcave, then demand is unique and continuous in p



existence follows because p>>0 implies bounded budget set




uniqueness follows from strict quasiconcavity of u

Properties of aggregate excess demand

if all u^i are continuous, strongly increasing, and strictly quasiconcave, then for all p>>0:




1. z is continuous at p


2. z(t p) = z(p) for all t > 0


3. p * z(p) = 0 (Walras' law)

Walrasian eqm

A price vector p* is called a Walrasian eqm if z(p*) = 0

Aggregate excess demand and Walrasian eqm

If:




1. z is continuous


2. p * z(p) = 0 for all p >> 0


3. If {p^m} is a sequence of price vectors converging to pbar != 0, and pbar_k = 0 for some k, then for some good k' with pbar_k' = 0, the associated sequence of excess demands in the market for good k', {z_k'(p^m)} is unbounded above




Then there is a price vector p* >> 0 such that z(p*) = 0.

Utility and aggregate excess demand

if all u^i are continuous, strongly increasing, and strictly quasiconcave and if aggregate endowment of each good is strictly positive, then excess demand z satisfies:




1. z is continuous


2. p * z(p) = 0 for all p >> 0


3. If {p^m} is a sequence of price vectors converging to pbar != 0, and pbar_k = 0 for some k, then for some good k' with pbar_k' = 0, the associated sequence of excess demands in the market for good k', {z_k'(p^m)} is unbounded above

Existence of Walrasian eqm

if all u^i are continuous, strongly increasing, and strictly quasiconcave and if aggregate endowment of each good is strictly positive, then there exists at least one price vector p* such that z(p*) = 0

Arrow's four things

U. Unrestricted domain


WP. Weak Pareto principle


IIA. Independence of irrelevant alternatives


D. Non-dictatorship

Unrestricted domain

The domain of f must include all possible combinationsof individual preference relations on X.

Weak Pareto principle

For any pair of alternatives x and y in X, if x Piy for alli, then xPy

Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives

Consider two sets of rankings R and R'. If everybody ranks x and y the same way in R and R', then the SOCIAL ranking of x and y in R and R' should be the same

Non-dictatorship

There is no individual i such that for all x and y in X, x Piyimplies x P y regardless of the preferences Rj of all other individuals j = i.

Arrow's impossibility theorem

If there are at least 3 social states, we can't come up with a social choice function that satisfies all of Arrow's four things

First welfare theorem

Consider an exchange economy (u^i, e^i)i \in I. If every consumer's utility function u^i is strictly increasing, then every Walrasian equilibrium allocation is Pareto efficient

Second Welfare theorem

Consider an exchange economy (u^i, e^i)i \in I with aggregate endowment >>0. Suppose u^i is continuous, strongly increasing , and strictly quasiconcave. Suppose xbar is a PE allocation for (u^i, e^i)i \in I and that endowments are redistributed so that the new endowment vector is xbar. Then xbar is a Walrasian equilibrium allocation of the resulting exchange economy (u^i, xbar^i)i \in I.

Another look at the second welfare theorem

Consider an exchange economy (u^i, e^i)i \in I with aggregate endowment >>0. Suppose u^i is continuous, strongly increasing , and strictly quasiconcave. Suppose xbar is a PE allocation for (u^i, e^i)i \in I. Then, xbar is a WEA for some WE pbar after redistribution of initial endowments to any feasible allocation e* such that pbar * e*^i = pbar * xbar^i for all i in I.

Existence of Walrasian Eqm with production

Consider the economy (u^i, e^i, theta^ij, Y^j)i \in I, j \in J.




If u^i satisfies:




1. continous


2. strongly increasing


3. strictly quasiconcave




And if Y^j satisifies:




1. 0 \in Y^j


2. Y^j is closed an bounded


3. Y^j is strongly convex (for all y1, y2 \in Y^j and all t \in (0, 1) there exists ybar \in Y^j such that ybar >= t y1 + (1 - t) y2 and equality does not hold)




And if y + endowment >> 0 for some production y \in sum Y^j, then there exists at least only price vector p* >> 0 such that z(p*) = 0.

First welfare theorem with production

Same as without production

Second welfare theorem with production

Suppose the conditions for existence of WE hold and (xhat, yhat) is PE. Then there are income transfers T1, ..., TI satisfying sum Ti = 0 and a price vector pbar such that:




1. xhat^i maximizes u^i(x^i) s.t. pbar * x^i <= m^i(pbar) + Ti


2. yhat^j maximizes pbar * y^j s.t. y^j \in Y^j

Dictatorial social choice function

A social choice function c is dictatorial if there is an individual i such that whenever c(R1, ..., RN) = x it is the case that x R^i y for every y \in X

Strategy proof social choice function

A social choice function c is strategy-proof when, for every individual, i, for every pair R^i and Rtilde^i of his preferences, and for ever profile R^-i of other's preferences if c(R^i, R^-i) = x and c(Rtilde^i, R^-i) = y then x R^i y

Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem

If there are at least three social states, then every strategy-proof social choice function is dictatorial

Pareto Efficient social choice function

A social choice function c is Pareto efficient if c(R1, ..., RN) = x whenever x P^i y for every individual i and every y \in X distinct from x

Monotonic social choice function

A social choice function c is monotonic if c(R1, ..., RN) = x implies c(Rtilde1, ..., RtildeN) = x whenever for each individual i and every y in X distinct from x, x R^i y implies x Ptilde^i y