• Shuffle
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Alphabetize
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Front First
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Both Sides
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Read
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
Reading...
Front

Card Range To Study

through

image

Play button

image

Play button

image

Progress

1/68

Click to flip

Use LEFT and RIGHT arrow keys to navigate between flashcards;

Use UP and DOWN arrow keys to flip the card;

H to show hint;

A reads text to speech;

68 Cards in this Set

  • Front
  • Back

Cardinals (hebrew letters)

one, two, three...., , These numbers count sizes.


(א).




Ordinals (greek letters)

Definition: Given a well-ordered set M, the "order type" or "the ordinal" of M is defined to be the unique ordinal number a such that there exists a bijection f: Oa -> M preserving order.


Ordinals: first, second, third... These don't indicate size, these keep track of order/position.


Whereas there is only one countably infinite cardinal, namely itself, there are uncountably many countably infinite ordinals, namely


ω, ω + 1, ω + 2, …, ω·2, ω·2 + 1, …, ω2, …, ω3, …, ωω, …, ωωω, …, ε0, ….




Cantor Theorems

1. Cardinality(natural numbers) < cardinality(ℝ)


2. The real numbers (ℝ) are uncountable.


3. There is no surjection A -> P(A); that is, |A| < |P(A)|

Cantor's Question

is |ℝ| = |ℝ^2|??


The answer is yes. Make a bijection from ℝ^2-> ℝ.


(x, y) -> f(x,y) where f(x,y) is the number created after rotating digits in x and y, where x and y are infinite and non-repeating.


if |A|=a and |B| = b, how big is Funct(A,B)?



= b^a

How big is P(A) if |A|=a?

|P(A)| = 2 ^a

Euclid

"The whole is greater than its parts". If x is a proper part of y, then |x|<|y|

How many points does a line segment have?

Aristotles Answer: "a line is not built out of points. Rather the line is prior and you can select points as needed".


"extremity of segment"


Cantors Transfinite Numbers

1. Cardinals: one, two, three.... These numbers count sizes.


2. Ordinals: first, second, third... These don't indicate size, these keep track of order/position.



for finite numbers, ordinals = cardinals.

Cantor Timeline Information

- PHD in Number Theory


- Moved to Hallee


- Habilitation in Number Theory


- early research in uniqueness of trig series.


- 70s uniqueness


- 71 finite exceptions


- 72 countable exceptions


- 78 stated continuum hypothesis but never proved


- 1902 Russell Paradox


- 1895/7 Burelli Paradox


proof: The real numbers (ℝ) are uncountable.

Any subset N of a countable set M={m1, m2, m3...} is at most countable. If we can find a subset of ℝ which is not countable, then a fortune ℝ cannot be countable. Look at: subset M of ℝ where m = (0 ,1] of all positive real numbers r with 0


Proof by Contradiction:


Suppose otherwise, that M is countable.


let M = {r1, r2, r3...} be a listing of M.


Write rn as its unique infinite decimal expansion without an infinite sequence of zeros at the end.


rn = 0.an1 an2 an3...


where ani ∈ {0, 1,..9} for all n and i.


Consider now the double infinite array


r1 = 0.a11 a12 a13...


r2= 0.a21 a22 a23...


.


.


.


rn= 0.an1 an2 an3 ...


.


.


.


For every n, chose bn ∈ { 1, ..8} different from ann. Then b = 0.b1 b2 b3... is a real number in our set M and hence must have an index, say b = rk. But this cannot be since bk is different from akk. (our contradiction)


Thus, the real numbers (ℝ) are uncountable.

Definition: Limit Points

A point x in X is a limit point of S if every neighbourhood of x contains at least one point of S different from x itself.

Cardinal Arithmetic Definitions ( +, *, ^)

let K and L be finite cardinals. Choose sets A, B such that |A|=K and |B| = L.




Addition: Note that A and B must be disjoint. then K + L = |A U B|




Multiplication: K*L = |A X B|




Exponentiation: K^L = |A^B| where A^B is the set of all functions from B to A.



for infinite:


K + L = max( K, L)


K * L = max(K, L)


Prove:


multiplication of cardinals numbers is commutative.

Proof:


choose sets A and B such that |A| = L and |B| = M.


Consider A X B and B X A.


|A X B| = L * M


|B X A| = M * L


Choose a bijection from A X B to B X A (which essentially reverses the ordered pair).


Thus, |A X B|= |B X A|since we found a bijection.


Therefore, L*M = M *L.


Ordinal Arithmetic definitions ( +, *)

Let a and b be two ordinals.




Addition:


Choose 2 disjoint well-ordered sets A, B with


ordinal(A) = a and ordinal(B) = b.


a + b = ordinal( AU B)



Multiplication:


define order of A X B where (a1, b1) < (a2, b2) if and only if b1 < b2



a X b = ordinal ( A X B)



** addition is associative but not commutative.

ω + 2 =

Let A = { a0, a1, a2...} and B ={ b0, b1}


|A| = ω and |B| = 2


ω + 2 = ordinal( A U B)


A U B = { a0, a1, a2, ....., b0, b1}


which can be correlated with


C ={ 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, ....ω, ω+1}


and ordinal(C) = ω+2



2+ ω =

Let A = { a0, a1, a2...} and B ={ b0, b1}


|A| = ω and |B| = 2


2+ ω = ordinal( B U A)


B U A = { bo, b1, a0, a1, a2...}


which can be correlated with


C = { 0, 1, 2, 3, 4....}


and ordinal(C) = ω


2* ω =

Let A = { a0, a1} and B ={ b0, b1, ...}


|A| = 2 and |B| = ω


define A X B listed in order


(a0, b0) (a1, b0) (a0, b1) (a1, b1) (a0, b2) (a1, b2)...


which can be correlated with


C = { 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5...}


and ordinal(C) = ω


ω * 2 =

Let A = { a0, a1, ...} and B ={ b0, b1}


|A| = ω and |B| = 2


define A X B listed in order


(a0, b0) (a1, b0) (a2, b0)...


(a0, b1) (a1, b1) (a2, b1)...


.


.


.


which can be correlated with


C = { 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5...ω, ω+1, ω+2.... ω+ω}


and ordinal(C) = ω+ω

Order in which number sets were defined in math

1. Complex Numbers in early 1800 as ordered pairs of real numbers ℝ


2. ℝ in 1872. Several who cleaned these up but the most notable were Cantor(defined with sequences) and Dedekind(defined with cuts).


3. , ℕ, ℤ: 1888 Peano Axiomd and Dedekind


4. Sets and sequences.

When are ordinals countable?

a, an ordinal number, is countable if and only if there is a countable set of order type a.

Peano Axiom Notation

Propositions:


U = or


∩ = and


∨ = true


∧ = False



classes:


U = Union


∩ = Intersection


∨ = Universe


∧ = Empty class



* dots tell us where to put parentheses


⊃ means implies


= means if and only if

Definition: Closed Set

A set is closed if it contains its' limit points.

Definition: well-ordered

each subset has a least element.



a well-order relation (or well-ordering) on a set S is a total order on S with the property that every non-empty subset of S has a least element in this ordering.



well-ordered sets have an ordinal order type. if the set is not well-ordered, then it doesn't have an ordinal.

Strict Finitism

Only a finite number of natural number exist


Classical Finitism

potential infinity exists but not actual infinity. The claim is that you can do math with this.

Continuum Hypothesis

there are no cardinals between aleph_1(size of the real numbers) and aleph_0 (size of the natural numbers). That


aleph_1 = 2^ aleph_0




This cannot be proved or disproved but <= can be proved.


Schroder-Bernstein Theorem (Cantors Version)
If |A| <= |B| and |B| <= |A| then |A| = |B|

Schroder-Bernstein Theorem

If A and B are sets, and if there are 2 injections f: A -> B and g: B -> A, then there exists a bijective function h: A->B.

Burali-Forti (1897) Paradox

The set of all ordinals is well-ordered. Or alternatively, the size of the set of all ordinals does not exists (causes a paradox).





Proof:


let Ω be the collection of all ordinals.


claim: Ω is well-ordered


let γ be the order type of Ω.


But γ ∈ Ω, so γ is also the order type of he segment Ω sub γ.


so γ < γ (which is a contradiction).

Russell's Paradox
The set of all set that which do not contain themselves.

Cantors Paradox (1899)

If S is a set, then |P(S)| > |S|



Proof:


let V be the universe


so every set is a subset of V.


so P(V) ⊆ V


so |P(V)|≤ |V|


But |P(V)|> |V|by Cantors theorem (which is our contradiction).

Axiom of Extensional


(ZF set theory)

Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same elements.


∀ x, y [ x = y ↔ ∀u (u ∈ x ↔ u ∈y)]



Axiom of Separation

(Zermelo) Whenever the propositional function F(x) is definite for all elements of a set M, M possesses a subset M_F containing as elements precisely those elements x of M for which F(x) is true.

Axiom of Choice (AOC)


(ZF set theory)

If x is a set of nonempty, pairwise disjoint sets, then there is a set y that consists of exactly one member of every set in x. Such a y is called a choice set for x.






Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of bins, each containing at least one object, it is possible to make a selection of exactly one object from each bin.




Axiom of Pairing

(ZF set theory)

For any x and y, the set {x, y} exists.

∀ x,y ∃ z ∀ u ( u ∈z ↔ u = x or u = y)



Axiom of Infinity


(ZF set theory)

Version 1:(Zermelo)


There is a set Z such that


1). the empty set is an element of Z


2). if a is in Z then {a} is also in Z.



Version 2: (Von Neumann)


There exists a set Z such that


1). the empty set is an element of Z


2). if a is in Z then a union {a} is also in Z.



Version 3: (Dedekind)


There exists a set Z and an injective non-surjective function S: Z-> Z

Axiom of Replacement


(ZF set theory)

Asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set.


∀ x ∈ A ∃! y F(x, y) → ∃ B ∀ y ( y∈ B ↔ ∃ x∈ A F(x, y))




axiom of replacement implies axiom of separation.

Axiom of Union

(ZF set theory)

For any x, the union of all the sets in x exists. This union is denoted ∪x
Axiom: Power set

(ZF set theory)

For any set x, its power set P(x) exists.
Axiom: Empty Set

(ZF set theory)

The empty set exists


Axiom of Regularity

(ZF set theory)

states that every non-empty set A contains an element that is disjoint from A.

∀ x ( x ≠ ∅ → ∃ y ∈ x ( y ∩ x = ∅ ) )




This does not generate new sets but prevents weird things from happening such as y ∈ x and x ∈ y.




This prevents: cycles and infinitely descending chains

Definition: Perfect
A subset of R is called perfect if it is non-empty and equal to its set of limit points.



* every perfect set is uncountable.

Definition of Ordinal

Cantor, von Neumann, ZF

Cantors Def: order types of well-ordered sets (abstraction)

Von Neumann: any ordinal is the set of all ordinals before it.


Zermelo-Frankel ST: An ordinal is a transitive set, all of whose members are also transitive. A set is Transitive if every member of it is a subset of it.


ex: {0, {0}} is an ordinal but {{0}} is not an ordinal



Cantors Definition: sets
|A| < |B| is there exists an injection, but not a bijection f: A -> B.


Cantors Definition: sets <=
|A| <= |B| is there exists an injection f: A -> B
Different Philosophers' definition of 3.

Frege


Russell


Zermelo


von Neumann


Peano

1). It is a symbol.

2). Frege: 3 is the class of all triples.


3). Russell: set of all triples of base types.


4). Zermelo:


∅, {∅}, {{∅}}, {{{∅}}}, .... so it is the number of parentheses.


5). von Neumann: 3 is defined as the segment of all cardinals less than 3.


3:= { 0, 1, 2}


= { 0, 1, {0, 1} }


= { 0, {0}, {0, {0}} }







6). Peano: 3 = S( S( S(0) ) )




Philosophers like Freges' definition because it is somewhat canonical. Set theoreticians like von Neumann. Mainstream math like Peano.

What does ZF, ZFC, and VBG stand for?
Zermelo-Fraenkl Set Theory

Zermelo-Fraenkl plus the axiom of choice.


von Neumann, Bearneys, and Godel.

Axiom of Reducability

Any function is coextensive with what he calls a predicate function (a function in which the types of apparent variables run no higher than the types of the arguments).

Axiom of Determinacy
States that this game is determined for every choice of x.


Axiom of Projective Determinacy
Asserts that our game is determined whenever x is a projective set.
Projective
A subset of R is called protective if it can be obtained in finitely many steps from a Borel subset of some R^n by applying the basic operations of taking complements and projections.
(FOL) Metavariables
Not part of the official syntax but these are used to describe the syntax.
(FOL) Expression
strings of symbols
(FOL) Term
is an expression that names something.

ex: 4+5 or x + 5




Definition: We define terms recursively as follows:


- Any declared variable symbol is a term


- Any declared constant symbol is a term


- if f is a declared function symbol of arity k, and if t1, t2, ..., tk are terms, then f(t1, t2, ..., tk) is a term


- if γ is a formula and if x is a variable symbol, then ix.γ is a term.

(FOL) Atomic Formula
Definition: We define atomic formula as follows.

-all declared boolean variables are atomic formulas


-both T and ┴ are atomic formulas


- if R is a declared relation symbol of arity k, and if t1, ...tk are terms, then R(t1,...tk) is an atomic formula.


- In particular, if t1 and t2 are terms then =(t1, t2) is an atomic formula

(FOL) Formula
is an expression that asserts something about certain terms. Formulas are either true or false.



ex: 4 + 5 = 9 or 7 < 4




Definition: We define formula recursively as follows.


- Any atomic formula is a formula


- if γ is formula, then (¬γ) is a formula


- if γ and ψ are formulas, then the following are also formulas:


(γ ∨ ψ) (γ ∧ ψ) (γ → ψ)


-if γ is a formula, and if x is a variable symbol, then (∀x.γ) is a formula, and (∃x.γ) is a formula.



(FOL) Context
is a description of all the constants, variables, and definitions in use, along with all axioms and other (temporary) assumptions that are made.



components:


1). symbol declarations: variables, constants, function symbols


2). definitions


3). Abbreviations and conventions


4). what variables are fixed


5). assumptions

(FOL) Sequent
is a formula together with a context.

Some of these will be axioms.

(FOL) Formal Rule of Inference
is a rule that takes as inputs zero or more sequents, and returns as an output another sequent.
(FOL) Proof
is a sequence of sequents, where each is either an axiom, a previously established theorem, or follows from previous sequents in the sequence by formal rules of inference.
(FOL) What are the 2 levels of syntax and what do they differ by?
2 levels: basic and extended syntax. Extended syntax uses abbreviations where basic does not. The user normally enters the extended version into the computer and then the computer converts it into the basic version and stores it.

ex: 3 + 4 + 5 this is the extended version since there are no ()


( (3+4) +5) this is the basic version since it is what the computer would interpret it as.

(FOL) what are the 5 types of symbols that can be declared?
1). Variable symbols. These are sometimes called individual variables, to distinguish them from boolean variables.

2). Constant symbols. These are sometimes called individual constants, to distinguish them from boolean constants.


3). function symbols.


4). Relation symbols.


5). Boolean variables.

Cantors Definition: Countably Infinite
a set A is countably infinite if

|A| = |natural numbers|

Prove

Cantors Theorem: |A| < |P(A)|
Proof:

1). first we show injective.


This is easy to see since we can make a function from A to P(A) such that a -> {a}. It is injective since by definition, P(A) contains all the elements of A and its subsets.




2). Now we show there is no surjection A-> P(A)


suppose f: A -> P(A).


We must show that f is not surjective (AKA there is something in the image not mapped to something in the domain).


Let B ∈ P(A) or B ⊆ A be defined by


B := { x ∈ A | x ∉ f(x) }




Claim: B is not in the image of f.


Case 1: Let x ∈ B, then x ∉ f(x) by definition of B.


Since x ∈ B and x ∉ f(x) we conclude f(x) ≠ B. This means that B is not in the image of any x ∈ B.


Case 2: Let x ∉ B. Then ¬(x ∉ f(x)) by definition of B.


so x ∈ f(x).


Since x ∉ B and x ∈ f(x), we conclude that f(x) ≠ B.




So for all x ∈ A, f(x) ≠ B.


Therefore, f is not surjective.

Prove

Theorem (one of Cantors): The set ℝ^2 of all ordered pairs of real numbers has the same size as ℝ.
Proof:

This will be proved by showing that there is a bijection from 1 set to the other.


It suffices to prove that the set of all pairs (x,y) 0< x, y, <= 1 can be mapped bijectively onto (0, 1].


Consider the pair (x,y).


Write x, y in their unique non-terminating decimal expansion.


ex: x = 0.3 01 2 007 08...


y = 0.009 2 05 1 0008...


(1-1) Separate the digits of x and y into groups by always going to the next nonzero digit, inclusive.


Now, we associate to (x,y) the number z ∈ (0,1] by writing down the first x-group, after that the first y-group, then the second x-group, and so on...


ex: z = 0.30090122050071080008...


Since neither x nor y exhibits only zeros from a certain point on, we find that the expression for z is again a non-terminating decimal expansion.


(onto) Conversely, from the expansion of z, we can immediately read off the premiere (x,y) and the map is bijective.



Dedekind Cuts`
Took the rational numbers and made a "cut". But every time you make a cut, there is always a number where you sliced.
Transitive Set
Assume S is a set of sets. S is transitive means that ∀ x, y if y ∈ x and x ∈ S then y ∈ S.