• Shuffle
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Alphabetize
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Front First
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Both Sides
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Read
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
Reading...
Front

Card Range To Study

through

image

Play button

image

Play button

image

Progress

1/44

Click to flip

Use LEFT and RIGHT arrow keys to navigate between flashcards;

Use UP and DOWN arrow keys to flip the card;

H to show hint;

A reads text to speech;

44 Cards in this Set

  • Front
  • Back
knowledge closed on entailment
if you know p and you know that p entails q, then you know q
knowledge closed on a relation R
a relation R is closed on a set S iff when x is in the set S and x bears R to y, then y is also in the set S.
if principles concerning closure are taken as steadfast, then there can be no concept of knowledge (since you wouldn’t know whether or not you are dreaming/perceiving properly). But if principles concerning closure are not accepted, then you can have knowledge of something without knowing whether or not you are a brain in a vat (Nozick O then ~BIV
Stroud’s principle
f you are to know p, and you realize q is incompatible with your knowing p, then you must know q is false
** know how Stroud uses this to tighten up the dreaming argument**
a priori knowledge
independent of experience
a posteriori knowledge
ependent on experience or empirical evidence
dogmatism
it’s appearing to one that P provides prima facie justification to believe P, whether or not one has independent justification to reject the skeptical hypothesis. If you have a sense-experience that P, you’re justified in believing P
**know how dogmatism bears on Moore’s proof and on the question of skepticism*
probability-increase account of confirmation
Evidence confirms Hypothesis iff E raises the probability of H. That is: the probability of H given E is higher than the probability of H alone.
White’s argument in relation to dogmatism: “this looks like a hand, this is a hand, this is not a fake hand” if you’re justified in believing it’s a hand (by perceiving it), then you are also justified in believing it’s not a fake hand by closure. If the probability raising model is true, then “this looks like a hand” must raise the probability of “this is not a fake hand”. But, it doesn’t. A fake hand also looks like a hand.
the thermometer model of knowledge
knowledge of fact is grounded in foundational knowledge of particular fact, which is in turn grounded solely in something that is not knowledge and not cognitive at all. All it takes to know is to get it right reliably in good circumstances
foundationalism
there are justified beliefs which aren’t justified by any further beliefs. There are foundational beliefs which all other beliefs are derived from
coherentism: the ultimate sources of justification for any belief lie in relations among that belief and other beliefs of the subject
formal foundationalism
epistemic justification has a certain sort of structure, namely one in which justification arises from the non or pre-justificatory.
If a belief has feature X, it is justified. If a belief is related in such and such ways to a justified belief, it is justified, too. All justification arises in this way.
how coherentism relates: just a type of formal foundationalism. If a belief coheres with one’s set of beliefs, it is justified.
substantive foundationalism
there are ultimate sources of justification, other than relations among beliefs. Traditionally, these additional sources pertain to the special content of the belief or its special relations to the subjective experience of the believer.
how coherentism relates: vulnerable to these examples (headache example)
supervenience
one sort of property supervenes on another when it occurs in addition to that property
**the supervenience of the epistemic on the non-epistemic is important (according to Sosa) because it implies that people identical in their non-epistemic features would also have to be identical in their epistemic features
S-evidence
according to Haack): mental (experiential and belief) state of A’s which are causally connected to A’s S-belief that p
C-evidence
(according to Haack): a set of propositions, claims, for each piece of S-evidence, you have a corresponding piece of C-evidence
~ if you have a belief based on S-evidence, then it takes you to some C-evidence. The belief is justified if C-evidence supports what you believe well enough
why experiential C-evidence is special: in cases of experience, C-evidence is always true. In cases of beliefs, it won’t always be true
traditional definition of knowledge
Justified True Belief
what a Gettier case is
you need to have justification, but a false belief (the justification doesn’t entail the truth). You then need to make the justification strong enough for knowledge and the false belief must be due to some element of bad luck. Next you add another separate element of luck, which makes the case true so you can have a JTB but not knowledge
**be able to identify one**
probabilistic theory
inductive inference amounts to inferring a conclusion when it is made probable by one’s evidence
causal theory
inductive inference amounts to concluding something about causal connections and then, on that basis, drawing further conclusions.
explanatory theory
inductive inference amounts to concluding something about explanatory connections and then, on that basis, drawing further conclusions
** be able to take theses different accounts, plus principle P, and apply them to examples
principle P
reasoning that essentially involves false conclusions, intermediate or final, cannot give one knowledge
subjunctive (counterfactual) conditional
had A been true, B would be true
Nozick’s “first go” theory of knowledge
1. p is true
2. S believes that p
3. if p weren’t true, S wouldn’t believe that p (~p ~(S believes p))
4. if p were true, S would believe that p (p S believes that p)
**be able to apply this to cases to determine its results (Gettier cases)**
goldfinch
Suppose looking out the window, you say you see a goldfinch in the garden. If you are asked how you know that, and you say it is a yellow bird, it is clear that this is not a case of knowledge. It could be a canary. If you don’t know that the bird is not a canary, then you don’t know that it is a goldfinch.
Witnesses
as a member of a jury you have been ruling out a suspect because he was a thousand miles away in Cleveland when the crime occurred. When you ask yourself how you know this, you would question your source of the belief. When scrutinizing your belief, you need not doubt everything you know about the case, just the man’s alibi, and the witness’s credentials.
Used to support his principle (listed above @ 2)
3 misprints on a page
A says there are three misprints, B is inclined to doubt it. How can A prove he is right? He could point to the three separate misprints. But A would not have proved that there were at least 3 misprints unless it was certain that what he pointed to were misprints. If this case is possibly certain, then it was certain there were hands in the places Moore indicated.
headache
I’m justified in believing I have a headache. But suppose that, while having the headache, I believe I didn’t have it, and that I “corrected” all of my other beliefs accordingly. Wouldn’t this set be just as coherent as my actual set, which includes the belief that I have a headache? Surely I’m not justified in believing I don’t have a headache.
~problem for coherentism
alien belief-forming processes
suppose some alien being had some other non-experiential mechanism for forming beliefs, and were frequently right. Wouldn’t they be justified? Yes, but not because of having experiences
~problem for versions of foundationalism that take the core of foundationalism to be a thesis about experiences
Smith & Jones Job
Suppose Smith and Jones have both applied for a job. Smith has strong evidence that D: “Jones is the man who will get the job, and Jones has ten coins in his pocket.” Smith was told by the president of the company that Jones would be selected, and Smith just counted the coins in Jones’ pockets. Preposition D entails E: that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket. Smith actually gets the job, but he too has ten coins in his pocket (unknown to him)
Smith & Jones & Brown Car
Smith has strong evidence that F: Jones owns a Ford. He remembers Jones always driving a Ford, and Jones just offered him a ride while driving a Ford. Smith has another friend, Brown. Smith decides to formulate three sentences at random. G: Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Boston. H: Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Barcelona. I: Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Brest-Litovsk. G, H, and I are all entailed by F. Smith has no idea where Brown is. H happens to be true, and Smith is justified in believing that because of his support for Jones’ Ford. However, this is not knowledge because his intermediate conclusion was false.
Omar and the mad fiend
Omar dies of a heart attack when lying down drunk in the street. Later a mad fiend comes by and decapitates him. You come along afterward (knowing nothing of the previous events). You conclude that Omar is dead.
The library case (Harmon)
you see Tom steal the book from the library. You know Tom well and know what he looks like. It turns out that later that day Tom’s mother testifies that Tom has an identical twin that was in the library. [compare to a case in which it is well known that Tom’s mother is a liar and there is no twin]
Donald in Italy (Harmon)
Donald tells you, sincerely, that he’ll be in Italy for the summer. For some reason, Donald changes his mind once he’s in Italy. He wants you to think he’s in San Francisco instead. He sends a friend in SF postcards in which he talks about SF, and then has that person mail the postcards to you. You’re about to open the letter. You believe he’s in Italy, and he is. [compare with a case in which the letter was written but never sent]
The assassination case (Harmon)
a political leader is assassinated. Those pulling off the coup announce on TV that the assassination attempt failed but that the leader was killed by a secret service agent by mistake. However, a journalist, before the announcement it made, publishes the true story in the paper. Jill reads only the story in the paper. (Other people also read the newspaper, but also see TV announcement, unlike Jill). [compare to a case in which the saboteur cuts the wires leading to the TV transmitter and the announcement is never made]
What drives the library, italy, and assassination cases (Harmon)
they all are missing evidence which would undermine your justification, while also showing that you can’t solve the Gettier problem by applying just inference to the best explanation and principle P. You also need to apply principle Q.
tank example
if someone is floating in a tank oblivious to everything around him is given beliefs (by direct electrical and chemical stimulation of the brain) that he is floating in a tank with his brain being stimulated, then even though that fact is part of the cause of his belief, he still doesn’t know that it is true.
The person does not have knowledge because his beliefs are not sensitive the the truth
Grandmother example
a grandmother sees her grandson is well when he comes to visit; but if he were sick or dead, others would tell her he was well to spare her grief. Yet this does not mean she doesn’t know he is well when she sees him.
We must explicitly consider methods of reaching a belief
Descartes’ Dreaming Argument
you don’t know you’re not dreaming, but you have to know this in order to have knowledge of the world through your sensory experiences, and so you don’t have knowledge of the world through your sensory experiences
Stroud’s Dreaming Argument
I remember waking up and haven’t gone to sleep since. We are automatically entitled to believing we are not asleep when we have reason to think otherwise.
Moore’s Hand Argument
there are two hands. If there are hands, there are external objects. There are external objects
White’s argument against dogmatism based on probability-increase theory of confirmation
dogmatism implies that one could gain justification to reject skeptical alternatives based on evidence that does not confirm that those alternatives are false. See #5 of “Concepts and Principles to Know”
White’s argument against dogmatism based on bootstrapping
f dogmatism is true, bootstrapping can be a way of learning that an instrument or faculty is reliable. Example of bootstrapping: “that one is red and it appears red”. This is silly because a test of this sort provides no evidence at all for the reliability of one’s color-vision.
Example: [A this looks red & B it is & C this looks blue & D it is] track record
B is verified by A alone and D is verifed by C alone
[my visual perception made no errors] no errors
[my visual perception is reliable] reliability
if dogmatism is true, you are justified in each of the components above, however this seems crazy so it must be wrong
Chisholm’s argument for foundationalism
there are beliefs that are justified, but they are not justified based on further beliefs. He thinks that when questioning what justifies a series of beliefs (Socratic method), there will arise an end point that is suitable. A problem may arise if the chain goes on infinitely (infinite regress), but Chisholm thinks there will always be a suitable stopping point, which will just be the original preposition repeated
ellar’s argument against the view that some of our knowledge fails to presuppose any other knowledge
to know something, your belief must have authority (other beliefs that stand behind it) and you must know that your belief has authority. This entails that any piece of knowledge presupposes other pieces of knowledge
Sosa’s Doxastic Ascent
if you are going to be justified in believing something, you must also have other justified beliefs which support it. These supplementary justified beliefs are a higher order argument which would be provided.