• Shuffle
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Alphabetize
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Front First
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Both Sides
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Read
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
Reading...
Front

Card Range To Study

through

image

Play button

image

Play button

image

Progress

1/56

Click to flip

Use LEFT and RIGHT arrow keys to navigate between flashcards;

Use UP and DOWN arrow keys to flip the card;

H to show hint;

A reads text to speech;

56 Cards in this Set

  • Front
  • Back
The Rules of Decision Act provides
"The laws of the several states, except where the Constitution or Acts of Congress otherwise require or provide, shall be regarded as rules of decisions in civil actions in the courts of the United States..."
What is the rule applied by the Court in the Guaranty Trust Co. v. York (1948) (p. 232)?
If the choice between a state and a federal rule is outcome-determinative, the rule is substantive for purposes of Erie; if not, it is procedural for purposes of Erie. In this case, the choice between the state and federal statutes of limitations is outcome-determinative, the statute of limitations is therefore Erie-substantive, and the Court therefore applied the state rule.
What is the nature of the rule applied in Byrd v. Blue Ridge Rural Elec. Coop (1958) (p. 235)? What is the rule?
It is a balancing test. In choosing between state and federal rules, if (1) the state's interest in its rule is law; (2) the federal interest in its rule is high; and (3) the probability of outcome-determinacy (POD) is not high, the federal rule should be applied. In that sense, the rule in question is Erie-procedural.
What type of argument is found in both Swift v. Tyson and in Erie v. Tompkins?
They both make arguments from statutory language (i.e. the language of the Rules of Decision Act) or, if you like, arguments from statutory language properly understood. (Erie also makes several other types of argument.)
When the Erie Court tells the story about the taxicabs, is it offering an argument? If so, what is it arguing for (or against)? And what kind of argument is it offering?
Yes it is offering an argument; an argument against the doctrine of Swift; an argument from bad consequences.
In Erie v. Tompkins (224), does the Court support its reversal of Swift v. Tyson with an argument from the actual, historical intention of a legislature. If so, explain.
Yes - the Erie Court cites the "recent research of a competent scholar" which has established that the Swift Court had been mistaken in its understanding of Congress' purpose in enacting the Rules of Decision Act.
In Erie v. Tompkins (224), does the Court support its reversal of Swift v. Tyson with an argument from bad consequences? Or, if you like, from "mischievous results"? If so, provide examples.
The Erie Court support its reversal of Swift v. Tyson with three different arguments from bad consequences: 1) the injustice arising from the forum shopping associated with the taxicab extravaganza. 2) "Swift v. Tyson introduced grave discrimination by non-citizens against citizens." and 3) continuing uncertainty as to the line between general law and local law. (225)
In Erie v. Tompkins (224), does the Court support its reversal of Swift v. Tyson with an argument from failed purposes? If so, provide examples.
Yes - the Erie Court argues that Swift v. Tyson Court intended to promote uniformity of law among the states but that the state courts persisted in their own opinions on questions of common law. (266-67)
In Erie v. Tompkins (224), does the Court support its reversal of Swift v. Tyson with an argument from the nature of the law? If so, explain.
Yes. The Erie Court argues that the Swift decision had rested, at least in part, on the earlier Court's misunderstanding as to the nature of law - namely its mistaken belief that there somehow existed a "general common law" that might be contrary to the settled law of a particular state.
In Erie v. Tompkins (224), does the Court support its reversal of Swift v. Tyson with a Constitutional argument? If so, explain.
Yes - the Erie Court argued that Swift v. Tyson represented an unconstitutional interpretation of the Rules of Decision Act because it gave to the federal courts the right to invade the rights of the states to declare the common law of the states.
In Erie v. Tompkins (224), does the Court support its reversal of Swift v. Tyson with argument from changed circumstances? If so, explain.
Yes. Most of the arguments made in Erie could be described as arguments from changed circumstances, including arguments from new learning and changed understandings (e.g., of Congressional intent, the consequences of the Swift rules, the nature of law).
What type of argument does the Court make in Guaranty Trust v. New York (1945) (232)?
It makes an argument from the distinction between two terms (substantive and procedure), properly understood for purposes of Erie.
In Hanna v. Plumer, what is the losing argument - stated as a syllogism?
(1) Where the choice of law is outcome determinative, the rules in question are Erie-substantive and state law applies, and where the choice of law is not, the rules in question are Erie-procedural and the federal law applies.
(2) the choice between the state and federal rules for service of process is outcome-determinative.
(3) therefore the service of process rule is Erie-substantive and the state rule applies.
In Hanna v. Plumer, how does the Court transform the case at bar from one in which the choice of law is outcome-determinative (and thus the state rules applies) to one in which the choice of law is not outcome-determinative (and thus the federal rule applies).
It argues (1) that outcome-determinacy, properly understood in light of the twin aims of Erie, is not outcome-determinacy at the time of the appeal (present in the case at bar) but outcome-determinacy when the plaintiff might have engaged in forum-shopping and (2) that outcome-determinacy, properly understood in the light of the twin aims of Erie, is not present in the case at bar.
A matched pair of arguments from statutory language, properly understood, is found in what two cases involving the vertical choice of law in diversity cases? Explain.
Swift v. Tyson and Erie v. Tompkins, both of which are making polar opposite arguments from the meaning of a single word (law) in the Rules of Decision Act.
Arguments from the (asserted) meaning of a text in light of what's previously been settled through earlier precedent or stare decisis can be found
Almost everywhere. Can you provide examples?
What examples of arguments based on the meaning of some term or distinction, properly understood, are found in Swift, Erie, Guaranty Trust, and Hanna v. Plumer?
In Swift and Erie, the Courts made opposite arguments from the meaning of the word "law," properly understood; in Guaranty Trust, the Court relies upon the distinction between "substance" and "procedure," properly understood for purpose of Erie; and in Hanna v. Plumer, the Court argued from the meaning of the term "outcome-determinative," properly understood in light of the twin aims of Erie.
Examples of arguments from historical intent attributed to some previous author, one from personal jurisdiction and one from the Erie series, one involving the intent of a legislature and the other involving the intent of an earlier court, are:
(1) The Court's argument in Erie from the intention attributed to Congress in passing the Rules of Decision Act and (2) the Shaffer Court's argument from the intention attributed to the International Shoe Court or the Hanna Court's argument from the intention attributed the Erie Court.
We've seen lots of arguments based on purposes or policies or intentions subsequently attributed to some earlier case. What was the earlier case whose purposes etc. were involved in Shaffer? Erie? Guaranty Trust? Hanna?
Shaffer argued from purposes, etc. attributed International Shoe: Erie, to Shift v. Tyson; Guaranty Trust, to Erie; and Hanna, to Erie.
My favorite example of an argument based on bad consequences, directed against some rule the speaker would have us reject is
Erie v. Tompkins, where the Court argues that the rule of Swift - which it would have us reject - produced bad consequences in the form of forum-shopping (e.g. the taxicab extravaganza) and certain forms of discrimination associated with diversity jurisdiction.
My favorite example of an argument based on a failed purpose, directed against some rule the writer would have us reject is (from the Erie chapter):
Erie v. Tompkins, where the Court argues that the rule of Swift - which it would have us reject - was intended (by Justice Story) to promote uniformity among the laws of the states but that it has failed in that purpose.
My favorite example of an argument based on changed circumstances and/or new learning, directed against some rule the writer would have us reject is (from the Erie chapter):
Erie v. Tompkins, where the Court argues that the rule of Swift - which it would have us reject - rested upon what we now know to be a misunderstanding of Congress' intent in passing the Rules of Decision Act and a misunderstanding of the nature of law.
My favorite example from something that isn't said is (from the Erie chapter):
in Byrd v. Blue Ridge (1958) where the Court argued that the failure of an earlier state court to announce the reasons for an earlier decision weighed against a party's argument that the earlier court had much cared about its result and that it had acted for a particular reason.
My favorite example of the counter-argument that someone else's argument (or rule, principle, or explanation) "proves too much," this one drawn from Justice Harlan's concurrence in Hanna v. Plumer, is
He argues that Guaranty Trust's outcome-determinative test...if, taken literally, proves too much [because] any rule, no matter how clearly "procedural," can affect the outcome of litigation if it is not obeyed. Thus a liberal application of "outcome determinacy" would cause us to label even purely procedural rules (i.e. those r.e. paper size) as "Erie substantive" and we all know that can't be right. Since that result is clearly wrong, so must be the literal reading of the test which produces that result. Note: this argument has been omitted from your casebook.
What claims are subject to heightened pleading requirement and, with respect to those claims, what is required?
Fraud and mistake. According to Rule 9(b), these claims must, for purposes of pleadings, be "stated with particularity."
Describe a situation in which a court might decide not to permit the amendment of pleadings and thus might hold one of the parties to an allegation, admission or denial known to be false?
Describe Zielinski or Beeck.
What does it mean to say that the amendment of a pleading "related back"? To what time does such an amendment "relate back"? Why does it sometimes matter?
To say that the amendment of a pleading "relates back" is to say that - for purposes of the statute of limitations - it is taken to have been filed on the date on which the original pleading was filed. It matters because, if the amendment does not relate back, the amended claim may otherwise be barred by the statue of limitations.
A judge's refusal to permit the amendment of a complaint could result in a decision that is otherwise contrary-to-fact or contrary-to-substantive-law if
A defendant is held to his admission, in the answer, of a fact later learned to be false (as might have happened in Aquaslide (394)), a defendant is barred from asserting an otherwise sufficient defense because it had not been pleaded as an affirmative defense (as happened in Layman (387)), a plaintiff is barred from asserting an otherwise good cause of action (as happened in Moore (400)) and might have happened in Bonerb (402)).
What is the standard that controls whether the amendment to a pleading "relates back"?
According to FRCP 15, an amendment to a pleading may "relate back to the date of the original pleading when...the claim or defense to be set forth in the original pleading" - sounds like STO, CNOF, SAOF relatedness).
If, in theory, preponderance of the evidence means 51% or more, what are the resistances or disinclinations that sometimes cause that number to drift higher?
Sometimes we resist statistical evidence, circumstantial evidence, market share evidence, lazy plaintiffs, and the idea of shifting costs onto defendant in really really close cases.
What is the effect of the Celotex case?
It established the proposition that a defendant seeking a motion for summary judgment need not prove the opposite of the elements of the plaintiff's case (on which the plaintiff will bear the burden of persuasion at trial) but need merely "show" that the plaintiff lacks proof of that element. Defendant seeking summary judgment not r3equired to demonstrate "I can prove that I'm not liable" but only to demonstrate that "the plaintiff can't prove that I'm liable.' In the meantime, a plaintiff seeking summary judgment must demonstrate "I can prove that he's liable."
Under what authority may the right to a jury trial in federal court arise? Must it be affirmatively asserted? May it be waived?
The right arises from the 7th Amendment and, in certain cases, from federal statute. It must be affirmatively asserted and, if not asserted, it may be waived.
With respect to the right to a jury rail, what is provided by the 7th Amendment?
The 7th Amendment preserves the common-law right to a jury trial as it prevailed in England in 1791, when the amendment was adopted. At that time there was a right to a jury trial in courts of law but not in courts of equity.
The 7th Amendment is understood to ensure the right to a jury trial...
(1) on issues that in 1791 would have been legal and not equitable and
(2) in cases involving claims that did not yet exist in 1791, on issues that are most nearly analogous to those that in 1791 would have been legal and not equitable.
If the parties seek legal and equitable claims simultaneously, the 7th Amendment ensures...
a right to a jury trial on all issues that are (or are like those that are) historically legal, including those issues that may be common to the legal and equitable claims.
If a party uses a procedural device that was in 1791 available only in equity (e.g. interpleader, class action, shareholder's derivative action, intervention, or declaratory judgment), will the federal court - for purposes of the right to a jury trial - overlook the fact that the device is historically equitable and then determine whether there is a right to a jury trial on the basis of whether the issues are legal or equitable?
The court will ignore the fact that the device is historically equitable and will decide on the basis of whether the issues are (or are like those that are) historically legal or equitable.
Has the 7th Amendment been held to be incorporated or implicit in the due process clause of the 14th Amendment and, as a result to control practice in state courts?
Nope.
Assume there are several different prime values that a society might pursue and that they include freedom of contract, equality, aggregate wealth, fairness, and the sovereignty of the states. If a decision-maker is maximizing one of those prime values, is it necessarily true that he is not maximizing the others?
Yes. Unless the two prime values really are identical - and the question assumes that they are different - maximizing one necessarily entails not maximizing the others. Thus someone who is committed to maximizing one (e.g. freedom of contract or fairness) can always be shown wiling to sacrifice another (e.g. equality or state sovereignty). That said, an argument from the two different prime values will sometimes, though not always, reach the same result.
EXTRA! An example of a counter-argument against someone else's argument from history and in which it is asserted that history ought not to be decisive (even if it is a good history) - provided by Oliver Wendall Holmes in texts we did not study - is
"It is revolting to have no better reason for a rule than that so it was laid down in the time of Henry IV. It is still more revolting if the grounds upon which it was laid down have vanished long since, and the rule simply persists from blind imitation of the past." Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 61 (1897).
Arguments against legal arguments based on "legal fictions" include (and here I'm just interested in your understanding the spirit of these objections)
"In English law, fiction is a syphilis, which runs in every vein, and carries into every part of the system the principle of rottenness." "Fiction of use to justice? Exactly as swindling is to trade." "The most pernicious and basest sort of lying." "It affords presumptive and conclusive evidence of moral turpitude in those by which it was invented and first employed." "It was never been employed but with a bad effect." Thus Jeremy Bentham warmed to this topic.
My favorite simplified example of an argument "X cannot account for Y" (using only numbers) is
If we take the data series "2, 4, 6, 8, 10" and the proposed rule "up by even numbers," the proposed rule can account for all the data. But if we take the data series "2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 11" and the proposed rule "up by even numbers," the proposed rule "cannot account for" 11. Similarly "up by even numbers" cannot account for the absence of 8 in "2, 4, 6, 10."
My favorite examples of "begging the question" through the dependency form of circularity is
(1) The Bible says that God exists.
(2) The Bible is true because it is the word of God.
(3) Therefore God exists.
The argument is circular because the conclusion (God exists) depends upon the truth of both premises while the second premise can be true if but only if the conclusion is true. Thus the truth of the conclusion depends on the truth of the premises while the truth of (one of) the premises depends on the truth of the conclusion.
My second example of "begging the question" through the dependency form of circularity, this one involving the value of trade names, is
(1) Courts must protect as property those things that are economically valuable.
(2) Trade names are economically valuable.
(3) Therefore the courts must protect trade names.
The argument is circular because the conclusion (courts protect trade names) depends upon the truth of both premises while the second premise (trade names are valuable) is true if but only if the conclusion is true. Thus the truth of the conclusion depends on the truth of the premises while the truth of (one of) the premises depends on the truth of the conclusion.
My favorite example of "begging the question" through the use of a pseudo-explanation is
Moliere's chemist's "explanation" that opium causes people to fall asleep because it has a "dormative power" - when the only evidence of that "dormative power" is the fact that it causes people to fall asleep. The "explanation" is presented as being useful and informative when, in fact, it is circular, totally uninformative and misdirects the reader's attention. Compare the contention that might have been made under Pennoyer that "International Shoe is subject to personal jurisdiction because it is "present" in the state of Washington." And compare "trade names deserve protection because they have economic value."
EXTRA! My favorite example of an argument from the (asserted) meaning of a text as supplemental by what's taken to be implied, this one drawn from Constitutional law is:
McCulloch v. Maryland (1819) where the Court implied Congressional power to incorporate a bank from the constitutional grant of other, broader enumerated powers.
EXTRA! My favorite example of an argument from the (asserted) meaning of a text as supplemental by what's taken to be reasonable, this one taken from antitrust law, is
Standard Oil Co. of N.J. v. U.S. (1911), where the Supreme Court declared that the Sherman Act's prohibition of "every contract, combination..., or conspiracy in restraint of trade" only extends to such arrangements as are in "unreasonable" restraint of trade.
EXTRA! My favorite example of an argument from the (asserted) meaning of a text as supplemented by an understanding of the nature of the text as a whole, this one drawn from Constitutional law is
McCulloch v. Maryland (1819) where the Court found that Congress had the constitutional power to incorporate a bank. It said that we "must never forget...that it is a constitution were are expounding," that it is in the "nature of such documents that they should speak broadly and must be read with flexibility," and that - read in that way - a law is "necessary and proper" if it is merely useful and appropriate.
EXTRA! One of my favorite examples of a "slippery slope" argument, this one drawn from Constitutional law and involving the commerce power and the destruction of our way of life, is
Hammer v. Dagenhart (1918) in which the Supreme Court argued that a law must be unconstitutional because "if Congress can thus regulate matters entrusted to local authority by prohibition of the movement of commodities in interstate commerce, all freedom of commerce will be at an end, and the power of the States over local matters may be eliminated, and thus our system of government practically destroyed."
EXTRA! One of my favorite examples of a "slippery slope" argument, this one drawn from Constitutional law and Justice Harlan's dissent in Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537 (1896) (upholding "equal but separate" railroad accommodations" is
"If a state can prescribe...that whites and blacks shall not travel as passengers in the same railroad coach, why may it not so regulate the use of the streets of its cities and towns as to compel white citizens to keep on one side of a street and black citizens to keep on the other? Why may it not...punish whites and blacks who ride together in street cars or in open vehicles on a public road or street? Why may it not require sheriffs to assign whites to one side of a court room and blacks to the other? And why may not states require the separation in railroad coaches of native and naturalized citizens of the United States, or of Protestants and Roman Catholics?" 557-58
EXTRA! One of my favorite examples of a "slippery slope" argument, this one draws from Constitutional law and involving the commerce power and childbirth, this one drawn from Justice McReynold's dissent in NLRB v. Jones & Laughlin (1938), is
A "more remote and indirect indifference with interstate commerce or a more definite invasion of the powers reserved to the states is difficult, if not impossible, to imagine. Whatever effect any course of labor discontent may ultimately have upon commerce is far too indirect to justify Congressional regulation. Almost anything - marriage, birth, death - may in some fashion affect commerce." Could we also say that he is saying the other side has "proven too much?"
EXTRA! A simple argument from exclusion involving letters is
Premise 1: X or Y.
Premise 2: Not X.
Conclusion: Therefore Y.

Formally this is a valid syllogism that is persuasive only if both premises are true.
EXTRA! You will sometimes hear statements like "the purpose of the antitrust law (or property law, contract law, tort law, all of common law, corporate law, etc.) is the maximization of aggregate wealth (or...)." Is such a statement "merely descriptive"? Explain.
Some will claim that such statements are not "normative" but are "merely descriptive." but they will usually be wrong. Such arguments are usually contestable and the only use to which they are usually put is entirely "normative" (e.g. the purpose of the property law is the maximization of aggregate wealth; we should adopt rule X because it maximizes aggregate wealth).
EXTRA! When one says that the purpose of some body of law is the maximization of aggregate wealth (or...), what is the meaning of "aggregate wealth"?
"Aggregate wealth (etc.)" is - simply but exactly - that which is always and substantially maximized by a Freely Operating Perfect Market (FOPM). That's why, for instance, these folks regard "market imperfections" (or externalities, etc.) as justification for legal action. It is neither the sum of everyone's bank accounts, nor the sum of the value of our assets. Neither is it the aggregate "utility" that utilitarians famously seek to maximize.
EXTRA! If one were seeking to maximize aggregate wealth, what would be the "right amount" of accidental injury (or air pollution or contractual breach or crime or poverty or rape)?
The amount of accidental injury (or air pollution or contractual breach or crime or poverty or rape) that would be produced (?) in a Freely Operating Perfect Market.
EXTRA! To whom and in what degree does a Freely Operating Perfect Market allocate goods?
To those who are willing and able to pay.
EXTRA! When one says that the purpose of some body of law is the maximization of aggregate wealth, what is the meaning of aggregate wealth?
The maximization of aggregate wealth is the maximization of that which is automatically maximized through the operation of a freely operated perfect market.