• Shuffle
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Alphabetize
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Front First
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Both Sides
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
  • Read
    Toggle On
    Toggle Off
Reading...
Front

Card Range To Study

through

image

Play button

image

Play button

image

Progress

1/73

Click to flip

Use LEFT and RIGHT arrow keys to navigate between flashcards;

Use UP and DOWN arrow keys to flip the card;

H to show hint;

A reads text to speech;

73 Cards in this Set

  • Front
  • Back

Set

A set is a collection of objects.

Elements

The objects that make up a set are called its elements (or members). If a is an element of the set A, then we write aA; if a does not belong to A, then we write aA.

Empty, Null, or Void Set

There is only one set that contains no elements, and it is called the empty set (or sometimes the null set or void set). The empty set is denoted by ∅. We also write ∅ = { }.

Natural Numbers

We use N to denote the set of all positive integers (or natural numbers); that is, N = {1, 2, 3, . . .}.

Integers Numbers

The set of all integers (positive, negative, and zero) is denoted by Z. So Z = {. . . ,−2,−1,0, 1, 2, . . .}.

Real Numbers

The set of real numbers is denoted by R, and the set of positive real numbers is denoted by R+.

Rational Numbers

Is a real number that can be expressed in the form of m/n for m,n ∈ Z and n ≠ 0 which is denoted as Q.

Irrational Numbers

Is a real number that is not a rational number which is denoted as I.

Cardinal Number of Cardinality

For a set S, we write |S| to denote the number of elements in S.


Examples:


- A = {1,2,{4,6}}; |A| = 3


- B = {1,3,∅,8}; |B| = 4


- |∅| = 0

Complex Numbers

A complex number is a number of the form a + bi where a,b ∈ R and i = √-1 which is denoted as C.

Subset

A set A is called a subset of a set B if every element of A also belongs to B. If A is a subset of B, then we write A ⊆ B. If A, B and C are sets such that A ⊆ B and B ⊆ C,then A ⊆ C.

Proper Subset

A set A is a proper subset of a set B if A ⊆ B but A ≠ B. If A is a proper subset of B, then we write A ⊂ B. For example, if S = {4, 5, 7} and T = {3, 4, 5, 6, 7}, then S ⊂ T . (Although we write A ⊂ B to indicate that A is a proper subset of B, it should be mentioned that some prefer to write A ⊆ / B to indicate that A is a proper subset of B. Indeed, there are some who write A ⊂ B, rather than A ⊆ B, to indicate that A is a subset of B. We will follow the notation introduced above, however.)

Union

The union of two sets A and B, denoted by A ∪ B, is the set of all elements belonging to A or B, that is:A ∪ B = {x : x ∈ A or x ∈ B}.

Difference between two sets

The difference A − B of two sets A and B (also written as A \ B by some mathematicians) is defined as A − B = {x : x ∈ A and x ∉ B},

Intersection

The intersection of two sets A and B is the set of all elements belonging to both A and B. The intersection of A and B is denoted by A ∩ B. In symbols, A ∩ B = {x : x ∈ A and x ∈ B}.

Disjoint

If two sets A and B have no elements in common, then A ∩ B = ∅ and A and B are said to be disjoint. The sets Q and I are also disjoint.

Complement

Suppose that we are considering a certain universal set U, that is, all sets being discussed are subsets of U. For a set A, its complement is A (Bar) = U − A = {x : x ∈ U and x ∉ A}.

Collection of Unions



Collection of Intersections

Index Set



Pairwise Disjoint

A collection S of subsets of a set A is called pairwise disjoint if every two distinct subsets that belong to S are disjoint. For example, let A = {1, 2, . . . , 7}, B = {1, 6}, C = {2, 5}, D = {4, 7} and S = {B, C, D}. Then S is a pairwise disjoint collection of subsets of A since B ∩ C =B ∩ D = C ∩ D = ∅.




On the other hand, let A = {1, 2, 3}, B = {1, 2}, C = {1, 3},D = {2, 3} and S = {B , C , D }. Although S is a collection of subsets of A and B ∩ C ∩ D = ∅, the set S is not a pairwise disjoint collection of sets since B ∩ C = ∅,for example. Indeed, B ∩ D and C ∩ D are also nonempty.

Cartesian Product



Negation

The negation of a statement P is the statement not P and is denoted by ∼P. Although ∼P could always be expressed as:


- It is not the case that P.

Disjunction

The disjunction of the statements P and Q is the statement P or Q and is denoted by P ∨ Q. The disjunction P ∨ Q is true if at least one of P and Q is true; otherwise, P ∨ Q is false. Therefore, P ∨ Q is true if exactly one of P and Q is true or if both P and Q are true.

Conjunction

The conjunction of the statements P and Q is the statement: P and Q and is denoted by P ∧ Q. The conjunction P ∧ Q is true only when both P and Q are true; otherwise, P ∧ Q is false.

Implication

A statement formed from two given statements in which we will be most interested is the implication (also called the conditional). For statements P and Q, the implication(or conditional) is the statement "If P, then Q" and is denoted by P ⇒ Q. In addition to the wording “If P, then Q,” we also express P ⇒ Q in words as P implies Q.




The implication can be also written as: P ⇒ Q ≡ (∼ P) ∨ Q.

Biconditional

For statements (or open sentences) P and Q, the conjunction(P ⇒ Q) ∧ (Q ⇒ P)of the implication P ⇒ Q and its converse is called the biconditional of P and Q and is denoted by P ⇔ Q. The biconditional P ⇔ Q is often stated as P is equivalent to Q.

Logical Connectives

The symbols ∼, ∨, ∧, ⇒ and ⇔ are sometimes referred to as logical connectives. From given statements, we can use these logical connectives to form more intricate statements.For example, the statement (P ∨ Q) ∧ (P ∨ R) is a statement formed from the given statements P, Q and R and the logical connectives ∨ and ∧.

Compound Statement

A compound statement is a statement composed of one or more given statements (called component statements in this context) and at least one logical connective. For example, for a given component statement P, its negation ∼P is a compound statement.

Logically Equivalent

Let R and S be two compound statements involving the same component statements. Then R and S are called logically equivalent if R and S have the same truth values for all combinations of truth values of their component statements. If R and S are logically equivalent, then this is denoted by R ≡ S. Hence P ⇒ Q and (∼ P) ∨ Q are logically equivalent and so P ⇒ Q ≡ (∼ P) ∨ Q.

Logical Equivalence: Commutative Laws

(a) P ∨ Q ≡ Q ∨ P


(b) P ∧ Q ≡ Q ∧ P

Logical Equivalence: Associative Laws

(a) P ∨ (Q ∨ R) ≡ (P ∨ Q) ∨ R
(b) P ∧ (Q ∧ R) ≡ (P ∧ Q) ∧ R

Logical Equivalence: Distributive Laws

(a) P ∨ (Q ∧ R) ≡ (P ∨ Q) ∧ (P ∨ R)
(b) P ∧ (Q ∨ R) ≡ (P ∧ Q) ∨ (P ∧ R)

Logical Equivalence: DeMorgan's Laws

(a) ∼ (P ∨ Q) ≡ (∼P) ∧ (∼Q)


(b) ∼ (P ∧ Q) ≡ (∼P) ∨ (∼Q)

Quantification

Quantification is a method for converting open sentences into statement. For example, let P(x) be an open sentence over a domain S. Adding the phrase “For every x ∈ S” to P(x) produces a statement called a quantified statement.

Universal Quantifier

The phrase “for every” is referred to as the universal quantifier and is denoted by the symbol ∀. Other ways to express the universal quantifier are “for each”and “for all.” This quantified statement is expressed in symbols by ∀x ∈ S, P(x) and is expressed in words by "For every x ∈ S, P(x)".

Existential Quantifier

Each of the phrases there exists, there is, for some and for at least one is referred to as an existential quantifier and is denoted by the symbol ∃. The quantified statement ∃x ∈ S, P(x)can be expressed in words by "There exists x ∈ S such that P(x)".

Characterization

Suppose that some concept (or object) is expressed in an open sentence P(x) over a domain S and Q(x) is another open sentence over the domain S concerning this concept. We say that this concept is characterized by Q(x) if ∀x ∈ S, P(x) ⇔ Q(x) is a true statement. The statement ∀x ∈ S, P(x) ⇔ Q(x) is then called a characterization of this concept. For example, irrational numbers are defined as real numbers that are not rational and are characterized as real numbers whose decimal expansions are nonrepeating. This provides a characterization of irrational numbers: A real number r is irrational if and only if r has a nonrepeating decimal expansion.

Axiom

A true mathematical statement whose truth is accepted without proof.

Theorem

A true mathematical statement whose truth can be verified is often referred to as a theorem, although many mathematicians reserve the word theorem for such statements that are especially significant or interesting.

Corollary

Is a mathematical result that can be deduced from, and is thereby a consequence of, some earlier result.

Lemma

Is a mathematical result that is useful in establishing the truth of some other result. Some people like to think of a lemma as a “helping result.”

Trivial Proof

Is a proof in which the conclusion of an implication is shown to be true without using the hypothesis.

Vacuous Proof

Let P(x) and Q(x) be open sentences over a domain S. Then ∀x ∈ S, P(x) ⇒ Q(x) is a true statement if it can be shown that P(x) is false for all x ∈ S (regardless of the truth value of Q(x)), according to the truth table for implication. Such a proof is called a vacuous proof of ∀x ∈ S, P(x) ⇒ Q(x).




In other words, the hypothesis of an implication is shown to be false.

Direct Proof

In a direct proof of P(x) ⇒ Q(x) for all x ∈ S, we consider an arbitrary element x ∈ S for which P(x) is true and show that Q(x) is true for this element x. To summarize then, to give a direct P(x) is true for an arbitrary element x ∈ S and show that Q(x) must be true as well for this element x.

Contrapositive Proof

For statements P and Q, the contrapositive of the implication P ⇒ Q is the implication (∼Q) ⇒ (∼P). For example, for P: 3 is odd and Q: 57 is prime, the contrapositive of the implication P ⇒ Q: "If 3 is odd, then 57 is prime" is the implication (∼P) ⇒ (∼Q): "If 57 is not prime, then 3 is even."

Proof by Cases

While attempting to give a proof of a mathematical statement concerning an element x in some set S, it is sometimes useful to observe that x possesses one of two or more properties. A common property which x may possess is that of belonging to a particular subset of S. If we can verify the truth of the statement for each property that x may have,then we have a proof of the statement. Such a proof is then divided into parts called cases, one case for each property that x may possess or for each subset to which x maybe long. This method is called proof by cases. Indeed, it may be useful in a proof by cases to further divide a case into other cases, called subcases.

Negation of ∀ x ∈ S, P(x)

~(∀ x ∈ S, P(x)) ≡ ∃ x ∈ S, ~P(x)


There exist x such that not P(X).

Negation of ∃ x ∈ S, P(x)

~(∃ x ∈ S, P(x)) ≡ ∀ x ∈ S, ~P(x)


For every x, not A(x)

Negation of P(x) ⇒ Q(x)

~(P(x) ⇒ Q(x)) ≡ P(x) ∧ ~Q(x)


P(x) and not Q(x)

Proof by Contradiction

In a proof by contradiction we assume, along with the hypotheses, the logical negation of the result we wish to prove, and then reach some kind of contradiction. That is, if we want to prove "If P, Then Q", we assume P and Not Q. The contradiction we arrive at could be some conclusion contradicting one of our assumptions, or something obviously untrue like 1 = 0.




This results in: P(x) ⇒ Q(x) ≡ P(x) ∧ ~Q(x) ⇒ Some Contradiction

Relationship

Let A and B be two sets. By a relation R from A to B we mean a subset of A × B. That is, R is a set of ordered pairs, where the first coordinate of the pair belongs to A and the second coordinate belongs to B. If (a, b) ∈ R, then we say that a is related to b by R and write a R b. If (a, b) ∉ R, then a is not related to b by R.

For the sets A = {x, y, z} and B = {1, 2}, the set R = {(x, 2), (y, 1), (y, 2) is a subset of A × B and is therefore a relation from A to B.

Reflexive

A relation R defined on a set A is called reflexive if x R x for every x ∈ A. That is, R is reflexive if (x, x) ∈ R for every x ∈ A.




Let S = {a, b, c} and consider the following six relations defined on S:


R1 = {(a, b), (b, a), (c, a)}


R2 = {(a, b), (b, b), (b, c), (c, b), (c, c)}


R3 = {(a, a), (a, c), (b, b), (c, a), (c, c)}


R4 = {(a, a), (a, b), (b, b), (b, c), (a, c)}


R5 = {(a, a), (a, b)}


R6 = {(a, b), (a, c)}.




The relation R1 is not reflexive since (a, a) ∉ R1, for example. Since (a, a) ∉ R2, itfollows that R2 is not reflexive either. Because (a, a), (b, b), (c, c) ∈ R3, the relation R3is reflexive. None of the relations R4, R5, R6 are reflexive.

Symmetric

A relation R defined on a set A is called symmetric if whenever x R y, then y R x for all x, y ∈ A. Hence for a relation R on A to be “not symmetric,” there must be some ordered pair (w, z) in R for which (z, w) ∉ R. Certainly, if such an ordered pair (w, z) exists, then w = z.

Transitive

A relation R defined on a set A is called transitive if whenever x R y and y R z, then x R z for all x, y, z ∈ A. Notice that in this definition, it is not required that x, y and z be distinct. Hence for a relation R on A to be “not transitive,” there must exist two ordered pairs (u, v) and (v, w) in R such that (u, w) ∉ R. If this should occur, then necessarily u = v and v = w (although perhaps u = w).

Equivalence Relation

A relation R on a set A is called an equivalence relation if R is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. Of course then, the equals relation R defined on Z by a R b if a = b is an equivalence relation on Z.

Equivalence Class

For an equivalence relation R defined on a set A and for a ∈ A, the set [a] = {x ∈ A : x R a} consisting of all elements in A that are related to a, is called an equivalence class, in fact, the equivalence class containing a since a ∈ [a] (because R is reflexive). Loosely speaking, then, [a] consists of the “relatives” of a.

Function

Let A and B be nonempty sets. By a function f from A to B, written f: A → B, we mean a relation from A to B with the property that every element a in A is the first coordinate of exactly one ordered pair in f.

Domain of a Function

Let A and B be nonempty sets. For the function f: A → B, the set A in this case is the domain of f, denoted by dom(f).

Codomain of a Function

Let A and B be nonempty sets. For the function f: A → B, the set B is called the codomain of f.

Image (Mapping) of a Function

If (a, b) ∈ f, then we write b = f(a) and refer to b as the image of a. Sometimes f is said to map a into b. Indeed, f itself is sometimes called a mapping.




For a function f : A → B and a subset C of A, the image f (C) of C is defined as f (C) = {f (x) : x ∈ C}.

Range of a Function

The set range(f) = {b ∈ B : b is an image under f of some element of A} = {f(x) : x ∈ A} is the range of f and consists of the second coordinates of the elements of f.

The Set of All Functions from A to B


One-to-one Function

We now consider two important properties that a function may possess. A function f from a set A to a set B is called one-to-one or injective if every two distinct elements of A have distinct images in B. In symbols, a function f : A → B is one-to-one if whenever x, y ∈ A and x ≠ y, then f(x) ≠ f(y). Thus, if a function f: A → B is not one-to-one, then there exist distinct elements w and z in A such that f (w) = f (z).

Injective Function

Injective functions are functions that are one-to-one.

Onto Function

A function f : A → B is called onto or surjective if every element of the codomain B is the image of some element of A. Equivalently, f is onto if f(A) = B.

Bijective Function

A function f: A → B is called bijective or a one-to-one correspondence if it is both one-to-one and onto. From what we mentioned earlier, if a function f: A → B is bijective and A and B are finite sets, then |A| = |B|. Perhaps it is also clear that if A and B are finite sets with |A| = |B|, then there exists a bijective function f: A → B. A bijective function from a set A to a set B creates a pairing of the elements of A with the elements of B.

Strong Principle of Mathematical Induction



Mathematical Induction

Set Properties: Commutative Laws

(a) A ∪ B = B ∪ A


(b) A ∩ B = B ∩ A

Set Properties: Associative Laws

(a) A ∪ (B ∪ C) = (A ∪ B) ∪ C


(b) A ∩ (B ∩ C) = (A ∩ B) ∩ C

Set Properties:Distributive Laws

(a) A ∪ (B ∩ C) = (A ∪ B) ∩ (A ∪ C)


(b) A ∩ (B ∪ C) = (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ C)

Set Properties: DeMorgan's Laws